[mod. f. as prec. + -IST: (perh. a. 17–18th–c. F. conceptualiste).] One who holds the doctrine of CONCEPTUALISM (in sense 1 or 2): esp. in History of Philosophy, applied to those who held opinions intermediate between those of the Realists and the Nominalists.

1

  (In med.L. called Conceptistæ: c. 1475, Petrus Nigri, Clipeus Thomistarum (1504) 56 a (Prantl). Una opinio est eorum qui dicunt quod universale est conceptus mentis, et isti nominantur conceptistæ.)

2

  Also, applied by Mill to one who holds that Logic is exclusively concerned with concepts.

3

1785.  Reid, Int. Powers, V. vi. Wks. 406/1. That universality which the Realists held to be in things themselves, Nominalists in names alone, they [a third party] held to be … in our conceptions. On this account they were called Conceptualists.

4

c. 1837.  Hamilton, Lect. Metaph. (1859), II. xxxvi. 316. The older Conceptualists [e.g., Locke, etc.] assert that it is possible to conceive a triangle neither equilateral nor rectangular,—but both at once.

5

1846.  Mill, Logic, I. vi. § 1. The opinion of the Conceptualists, that a proposition is the expression of a relation between two ideas. Ibid., I. vi. § 3, note. Where a Conceptualist says that a name or a proposition expresses our Idea of a thing, I should generally say (instead of our Idea) our Knowledge, or Belief, concerning the thing itself.

6

1855.  Milman, Lat. Chr. (1872), IV. 365. John of Salisbury, in his Polycraticus, is a manifest, if not avowed Conceptualist.

7

  attrib.  1858.  J. Martineau, Studies Chr., 173. The mediatorial theology of Christendom,—a theology which never could have sprung up if our present conceptualist and nominalist notions had always prevailed.

8

1884.  Athenæum, 14 June, 752/3. The conceptualist school which once ruled English logic under the influence of Hamilton and Mansel.

9

  Hence Conceptualistic a., pertaining to, or of the nature of, conceptualism.

10

In mod. Dicts.

11